TALK SIX - SIN & GRACE (180m)
---- AV - Les Miserables: Castle on the Cloud - Cosette
---- City of God - Bk 12: Ch 6-7
---- City of God - Bk 14: Ch 7
---- ST: P1, Q49, A2; P1, Q49, A1; P1, Q95 A1; P2-1, Q8, A1; P2-1, Q18, A1; P2-1, Q18, A2; P2-1, Q18, A3; P2-1, Q18, A4; P2-1, Q18, A9; P2-1, Q74, A1; P2-1, Q74, A2; P2-1, Q74, A3; P2-1, Q74, A5; P2-1, Q74, A8; P2-1, Q110, A1; P2-1, Q110, A2; P2-1, Q110, A3;
---- Summa Contra Gentiles B3, A159
---- Catechism - 1846-1869
BOOK XII CHAPTER 6
WHAT THE CAUSE OF THE BLESSEDNESS OF THE GOOD ANGELS IS, AND WHAT
THE CAUSE OF THE MISERY OF THE WICKED
Thus the true cause of the blessedness of the good angels is found
to be this, that they cleave to Him who supremely is. And if we ask the cause
of the misery of the bad, it occurs to us, and not unreasonably, that they are
miserable because they have forsaken Him who supremely is, and have turned to
themselves who have no such essence. And this vice, what else is it called than
pride? For "pride is the beginning of sin." They were unwilling,
then, to preserve their strength for God: and as adherence to God was the
condition of their enjoying an ampler being, they diminished it by preferring
themselves to Him. This was the first defect, and the first impoverishment, and
the first flaw of their nature, which was created, not indeed supremely
existent, but finding its blessedness in the enjoyment of the Supreme Being;
whilst by abandoning Him it should become, not indeed no nature at all, but a
nature with a less ample existence, and therefore wretched.
If the further question be asked, What was the efficient cause of
their evil will? there is none. For what is it which makes the will bad, when
it is the will itself which makes the action bad? And consequently the bad will
is the cause of the bad action, but nothing is the efficient cause of the bad
will. For if anything is the cause, this thing either has or has not a will. If
it has, the will is either good or bad. If good, who is so left to himself as
to say that a good will makes a will bad? For in this case a good will would be
the cause of sin; a most absurd supposition. On the other hand, if this
hypothetical thing has a bad will, I wish to know what made it so; and that we
may not go on forever, I ask at once, what made the first evil will bad? For
that is not the first which was itself corrupted by an evil will, but that is
the first which was made evil by no other will. For if it were preceded by that
which made it evil, that will was first which made the other evil. But if it is
replied, "Nothing made it evil; it always was evil," I ask if it has
been existing in some nature. For if not, then it did not exist at all; and if
it did exist in some nature, then it vitiated and corrupted it, and injured it,
and consequently deprived it of good. And therefore the evil will could not
exist in an evil nature, but in a nature at once good and mutable, which this
vice could injure. For if it did no injury, it was no vice; and consequently
the will in which it was, could not be called evil. But if it did injury, it
did it by taking away or diminishing good. And therefore there could not be
from eternity, as was suggested, an evil will in that thing in which there had
been previously a natural good, which the evil will was able to diminish by
corrupting it. If, then, it was not from eternity, who, I ask, made it? The
only thing that can be suggested in reply is, that something which itself had
no will, made the will evil. I ask, then, whether this thing was superior, inferior,
or equal to it? If superior, then it is better. How, then, has it no will, and
not rather a good will? The same reasoning applies if it was equal; for so long
as two things have equally a good will, the one cannot produce in the other an
evil will. Then remains the supposition that that which corrupted the will of
the angelic nature which first sinned, was itself an inferior thing without a
will. But that thing, be it of the lowest and most earthly kind, is certainly
itself good, since it is a nature and being, with a form and rank of its own in
its own kind and order. How, then, can a good thing be the efficient cause of
an evil will? How, I say, can good be the cause of evil? For when the will
abandons what is above itself, and turns to what is lower, it becomes evil ‹ not because that is
evil to which it turns, but because the turning itself is wicked. Therefore it
is not an inferior thing which has made the will evil, but it is itself which
has become so by wickedly and inordinately desiring an inferior thing. For if
two men, alike in physical and moral constitution, see the same corporal
beauty, and one of them is excited by the sight to desire an illicit enjoyment
while the other steadfastly maintains a modest restraint of his will, what do
we suppose brings it about, that there is an evil will in the one and not in
the other? What produces it in the man in whom it exists? Not the bodily
beauty, for that was presented equally to the gaze of both, and vet did not
produce in both an evil will. Did the flesh of the one cause the desire as he
looked? But why did not the flesh of the other? Or was it the disposition? But
why not the disposition of both? For we are supposing that both were of a like
temperament of body and soul. Must we, then, say that the one was tempted by a
secret suggestion of the evil spirit? As if it was not by Iris own will that he
consented to this suggestion and to any inducement whatever! This consent,
then, this evil will which he presented to the evil suasive influence, ‹ what was the cause
of it, we ask? For, not to delay on such a difficulty as this, if both are
tempted equally and one yields and consents to the temptation while the other
remains unmoved by it, what other account can we give of the matter than this,
that the one is willing, the other unwilling, to fall away from chastity? And
what causes this but their own wills, in cases at least such as we are
supposing, where the temperament is identical? The same beauty was equally
obvious to the eyes of both; the same secret temptation pressed on both with
equal violence. However minutely we examine the case, therefore, we can discern
nothing which caused the will of the one to be evil. For if we say that the man
himself made his will evil, what was the man himself before his will was evil
but a good nature created by God, the unchangeable good? Here are two men who,
before the temptation, were alike in body and soul, and of whom one yielded to
the tempter who persuaded him, while the other could not be persuaded to desire
that lovely body which was equally before the eyes of both. Shall we say of the
successfully tempted man that he corrupted his own will, since he was certainly
good before his will became bad? Then, why did he do so? Was it because his
will was a nature, or because it was made of nothing? We shall find that the
latter is the case. For if a nature is the cause of an evil will, what else can
we say than that evil arises from good or that good is the cause of evil? And
how can it come to pass that a nature, good though mutable, should produce any
evil ‹ that is to say, should make the will itself wicked?
BOOK XII CHAPTER 7 THAT WE OUGHT NOT TO EXPECT TO FIND ANY
EFFICIENT CAUSE OF THE EVIL WILL
Let no one, therefore, look for an efficient cause of the evil will;
for it is not efficient, but deficient, as the will itself is not an effecting
of something, but a defect. For defection from that which supremely is, to that
which has less of being, ‹ this is to begin to have an evil will. Now, to seek to discover the
causes of these defections, ‹ causes, as I have said, not efficient, but
deficient, ‹ is as if some one sought to see darkness, or hear silence. Yet
both of these are known by us, and the former by means only of the eye, the
latter only by the ear; but not by their positive actuality, but by their want
of it. Let no one, then seek to know from me what I know that I do not know;
unless he perhaps wishes to learn to be ignorant of that of which all we know
is, that it cannot be known. For those things which are known not by their
actuality, but by their want of it, are known, if our expression may be allowed
and understood, by not knowing them, that by knowing them they may be not
known. For when the eyesight surveys objects that strike the sense, it nowhere
sees darkness but where it begins, not to see. And so no other sense but the
ear can perceive silence, and yet it is only perceived by not hearing. Thus,
too, our mind perceives intelligible forms by understanding them; but when they
are deficient, it knows them by not knowing them; for "who can understand
defects?"
BOOK XIV CHAPTER 7
THAT THE WORDS LOVE AND REGARD (AMOR AND DILECTIO) ARE IN
SCRIPTURE USED INDIFFERENTLY OF GOOD AND EVIL AFFECTION
He who resolves to love God, and to love his neighbor as himself,
not according to man but according to God, is on account of this love said to
be of a good will; and this is in Scripture more commonly called charity, but
it is also, even in the same books, called love. For the apostle says that the
man to be elected as a ruler of the people must be a lover of good. And when
the Lord Himself had asked Peter, "Hast thou a regard for me (diligis)
more than these?" Peter replied, "Lord, Thou knowest that I love
(amo) Thee." And again a second time the Lord asked not whether Peter
loved (amaret) Him, but whether he had a regard (diligeret) for Him, and, he
again answered, "Lord, Thou knowest that I love (amo) Thee." But on
the third interrogation the Lord Himself no longer says, "Hast thou a
regard (diligis) for me, "but "Lovest thou (amas) me?" And then
the evangelist adds, "Peter was grieved because He said unto him the third
time, Lovest thou (amas) me?" though the Lord had not said three times but
only once, "Lovest thou (amas) me?" and twice "Diligis me?"
from which we gather that, even when the Lord said "diligis," He used
an equivalent for "amas." Peter, too, throughout used one word for
the one thing, and the third time also replied, "Lord, Thou knowest all
things, Thou knowest that I love (amo) Thee."
I have judged it right to mention this, because some are of
opinion that charity or regard (dilectio) is one thing, love (amor) another.
They say that dilectio is used of a good affection, amor of an evil love. But
it is very certain that even secular literature knows no such distinction.
However, it is for the philosophers to determine whether and how they differ,
though their own writings sufficiently testify that they make great account of
love (amor) placed on good objects, and even on God Himself. But we wished to
show that the Scriptures of our religion, whose authority we prefer to all
writings whatsoever, make no distinction between amor, dilectio, and caritas;
and we have already shown that amor is used in a good connection. And if any
one fancy that amor is no doubt used both of good and bad loves, but that
dilectio is reserved for the good only, let him remember what the psalm says,
"He that loveth (diligit) iniquity hateth his own soul;" and the
words of the Apostle John, "If any man love (diligere) the world, the love
(dilectio) of the Father is not in him." Here you have in one passage
dilectio used both in a good and a bad sense. And if any one demands an
instance of amor being used in a bad sense (for we have already shown its use
in a good sense), let him read the words, "For men shall be lovers
(amantes) of their own selves, lovers (amatores) of money." The right will
is, therefore, well-directed love, and the wrong will is ill-directed love.
Love, then, yearning to have what is loved, is desire; and having and enjoying
it, is joy; fleeing what is opposed to it, it is fear; and feeling what is
opposed to it, when it has befallen it, it is sadness. Now these motions are
evil if the love is evil; good if the love is good. What we assert let us prove
from Scripture. The apostle "desires to depart, and to be with
Christ." And, "My soul desired to long for Thy judgments;" or if
it is more appropriate to say, "My soul longed to desire Thy
judgments." And, "The desire of wisdom bringeth to a kingdom."
Yet there has always obtained the usage of understanding desire and
concupiscence in a bad sense if the object be not defined. But joy is used in a
good sense: "Be glad in the Lord, and rejoice, ye righteous." And,
"Thou hast put gladness in my heart." And, "Thou wilt fill me
with joy with Thy countenance." Fear is used in a good sense by the
apostle when he says, "Work out your salvation with fear and
trembling." And, "Be not high-minded, but fear." And, "I
fear, lest by any means, as the serpent be-Culled Eve through his subtilty, so
your minds should be corrupted from the simplicity that is in Christ." But
with respect to sadness, which Cicero prefer to calls sickness (oegritudo), and
Virgil pain (dolor) (as he says, "Dolent gaudentque"), but which I
prefer to call sorrow, because sickness and pain are more commonly used to
express bodily suffering, ‹ with respect to this emotion, I say, the
question whether it can be used in a good sense is more difficult.
================
P1, Q49, A1 - Whether good can be the cause of evil?
Objection 1: It would seem that good cannot be the cause of evil.
For it is said (Mt. 7:18): "A good tree cannot bring forth evil
fruit."
Objection 2: Further, one contrary cannot be the cause of another.
But evil is the contrary to good. Therefore good cannot be the cause of evil.
Objection 3: Further, a deficient effect can proceed only from a
deficient cause. But evil is a deficient effect. Therefore its cause, if it has
one, is deficient. But everything deficient is an evil. Therefore the cause of
evil can only be evil.
Objection 4: Further, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that evil has
no cause. Therefore good is not the cause of evil.
On the contrary, Augustine says (Contra Julian. i, 9): "There
is no possible source of evil except good."
I answer that, It must be said that every evil in some way has a
cause. For evil is the absence of the good, which is natural and due to a
thing. But that anything fail from its natural and due disposition can come
only from some cause drawing it out of its proper disposition. For a heavy
thing is not moved upwards except by some impelling force; nor does an agent
fail in its action except from some impediment. But only good can be a cause;
because nothing can be a cause except inasmuch as it is a being, and every
being, as such, is good.
And if we consider
the special kinds of causes, we see that the agent, the form, and the end,
import some kind of perfection which belongs to the notion of good. Even
matter, as a potentiality to good, has the nature of good. Now that good is the
cause of evil by way of the material cause was shown above (Question [48],
Article [3]). For it was shown that good is the subject of evil. But evil has
no formal cause, rather is it a privation of form; likewise, neither has it a
final cause, but rather is it a privation of order to the proper end; since not
only the end has the nature of good, but also the useful, which is ordered to
the end. Evil, however, has a cause by way of an agent, not directly, but
accidentally.
In proof of this, we
must know that evil is caused in the action otherwise than in the effect. In
the action evil is caused by reason of the defect of some principle of action,
either of the principal or the instrumental agent; thus the defect in the
movement of an animal may happen by reason of the weakness of the motive power,
as in the case of children, or by reason only of the ineptitude of the
instrument, as in the lame. On the other hand, evil is caused in a thing, but
not in the proper effect of the agent, sometimes by the power of the agent,
sometimes by reason of a defect, either of the agent or of the matter. It is
caused by reason of the power or perfection of the agent when there necessarily
follows on the form intended by the agent the privation of another form; as,
for instance, when on the form of fire there follows the privation of the form
of air or of water. Therefore, as the more perfect the fire is in strength, so
much the more perfectly does it impress its own form, so also the more perfectly
does it corrupt the contrary. Hence that evil and corruption befall air and
water comes from the perfection of the fire: but this is accidental; because
fire does not aim at the privation of the form of water, but at the bringing in
of its own form, though by doing this it also accidentally causes the other.
But if there is a defect in the proper effect of the fire---as, for instance,
that it fails to heat---this comes either by defect of the action, which
implies the defect of some principle, as was said above, or by the
indisposition of the matter, which does not receive the action of the fire, the
agent. But this very fact that it is a deficient being is accidental to good to
which of itself it belongs to act. Hence it is true that evil in no way has any
but an accidental cause; and thus is good the cause of evil.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P1, Q49, A2 - Whether the supreme good, God, is the cause of evil?
Objection 1: It would seem that the supreme good, God, is the
cause of evil. For it is said (Is. 45:5,7): "I am the Lord, and there is
no other God, forming the light, and creating darkness, making peace, and
creating evil." And Amos 3:6, "Shall there be evil in a city, which
the Lord hath not done?"
Objection 2: Further, the effect of the secondary cause is reduced
to the first cause. But good is the cause of evil, as was said above (Article
[1]). Therefore, since God is the cause of every good, as was shown above
(Question [2], Article [3]; Question [6], Articles [1],4), it follows that also
every evil is from God.
Objection 3: Further, as is said by the Philosopher (Phys. ii,
text 30), the cause of both safety and danger of the ship is the same. But God
is the cause of the safety of all things. Therefore He is the cause of all
perdition and of all evil.
On the contrary, Augustine says (Questions. 83, qu. 21), that,
"God is not the author of evil because He is not the cause of tending to
not-being."
I answer that, As appears from what was said (Article [1]), the
evil which consists in the defect of action is always caused by the defect of
the agent. But in God there is no defect, but the highest perfection, as was
shown above (Question [4], Article [1]). Hence, the evil which consists in
defect of action, or which is caused by defect of the agent, is not reduced to
God as to its cause.
But the evil which consists in the corruption of some things is
reduced to God as the cause. And this appears as regards both natural things
and voluntary things. For it was said (Article [1]) that some agent inasmuch as
it produces by its power a form to which follows corruption and defect, causes
by its power that corruption and defect. But it is manifest that the form which
God chiefly intends in things created is the good of the order of the universe.
Now, the order of the universe requires, as was said above (Question [22],
Article [2], ad 2; Question [48], Article [2]), that there should be some
things that can, and do sometimes, fail. And thus God, by causing in things the
good of the order of the universe, consequently and as it were by accident,
causes the corruptions of things, according to 1 Kgs. 2:6: "The Lord
killeth and maketh alive." But when we read that "God hath not made
death" (Wis. 1:13), the sense is that God does not will death for its own
sake. Nevertheless the order of justice belongs to the order of the universe;
and this requires that penalty should be dealt out to sinners. And so God is
the author of the evil which is penalty, but not of the evil which is fault, by
reason of what is said above.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P1, Q49, A1 - Whether there be one supreme evil which is the cause
of every evil?
Objection 1: It would seem that there is one supreme evil which is
the cause of every evil. For contrary effects have contrary causes. But
contrariety is found in things, according to Ecclus. 33:15: "Good is set
against evil, and life against death; so also is the sinner against a just
man." Therefore there are many contrary principles, one of good, the other
of evil.
Objection 2: Further, if one contrary is in nature, so is the
other. But the supreme good is in nature, and is the cause of every good, as
was shown above (Question [2], Article [3]; Question [6], Articles [2],4).
Therefore, also, there is a supreme evil opposed to it as the cause of every
evil.
Objection 3: Further, as we find good and better things, so we
find evil and worse. But good and better are so considered in relation to what
is best. Therefore evil and worse are so considered in relation to some supreme
evil.
Objection 4: Further, everything participated is reduced to what
is essential. But things which are evil among us are evil not essentially, but
by participation. Therefore we must seek for some supreme essential evil, which
is the cause of every evil.
Objection 5: Further, whatever is accidental is reduced to that
which is "per se." But good is the accidental cause of evil.
Therefore, we must suppose some supreme evil which is the "per se"
cause of evils. Nor can it be said that evil has no "per se" cause,
but only an accidental cause; for it would then follow that evil would not
exist in the many, but only in the few.
Objection 6: Further, the evil of the effect is reduced to the
evil of the cause; because the deficient effect comes from the deficient cause,
as was said above (Articles [1],2). But we cannot proceed to infinity in this
matter. Therefore, we must suppose one first evil as the cause of every evil.
On the contrary, The supreme good is the cause of every being, as
was shown above (Question [2], Article [3]; Question [6], Article [4]).
Therefore there cannot be any principle opposed to it as the cause of evils.
I answer that, It appears from what precedes that there is no one
first principle of evil, as there is one first principle of good.
First, indeed, because the first principle of good is essentially
good, as was shown above (Question [6], Articles [3],4). But nothing can be
essentially bad. For it was shown above that every being, as such, is good
(Question [5], Article [3]); and that evil can exist only in good as in its
subject (Question [48], Article [3]).
Secondly, because the first principle of good is the highest and
perfect good which pre-contains in itself all goodness, as shown above
(Question [6], Article [2]). But there cannot be a supreme evil; because, as
was shown above (Question [48], Article [4]), although evil always lessens
good, yet it never wholly consumes it; and thus, while good ever remains, nothing
can be wholly and perfectly bad. Therefore, the Philosopher says (Ethic. iv, 5)
that "if the wholly evil could be, it would destroy itself"; because
all good being destroyed (which it need be for something to be wholly evil),
evil itself would be taken away, since its subject is good.
Thirdly, because the very nature of evil is against the idea of a
first principle; both because every evil is caused by good, as was shown above
(Article [1]), and because evil can be only an accidental cause, and thus it
cannot be the first cause, for the accidental cause is subsequent to the direct
cause.
Those, however, who upheld two first principles, one good and the
other evil, fell into this error from the same cause, whence also arose other
strange notions of the ancients; namely, because they failed to consider the
universal cause of all being, and considered only the particular causes of
particular effects. For on that account, if they found a thing hurtful to
something by the power of its own nature, they thought that the very nature of
that thing was evil; as, for instance, if one should say that the nature of
fire was evil because it burnt the house of a poor man. The judgment, however,
of the goodness of anything does not depend upon its order to any particular
thing, but rather upon what it is in itself, and on its order to the whole
universe, wherein every part has its own perfectly ordered place, as was said
above (Question [47], Article [2], ad 1).
Likewise, because they found two contrary particular causes of two
contrary particular effects, they did not know how to reduce these contrary
particular causes to the universal common cause; and therefore they extended
the contrariety of causes even to the first principles. But since all
contraries agree in something common, it is necessary to search for one common
cause for them above their own contrary proper causes; as above the contrary
qualities of the elements exists the power of a heavenly body; and above all
things that exist, no matter how, there exists one first principle of being, as
was shown above (Question [2], Article [3]).
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P1, Q95 A1 - Whether the first man was created in grace?
I answer that, Some say that man was not created in grace; but
that it was bestowed on him
subsequently before sin: and many authorities of the Saints declare that
man possessed grace in the state
of innocence.
But the very rectitude of the primitive state, wherewith man was
endowed by God, seems to require that, as others say, he was created in grace,
according to Eccles. 7:30, "God made man right." For this rectitude
consisted in his reason being subject to God, the lower powers to reason, and
the body to the soul: and the first subjection was the cause of both the second
and the third; since while reason was subject to God, the lower powers remained
subject to reason, as Augustine says [*Cf. De Civ. Dei xiii, 13; De Pecc.
Merit. et Remiss. i, 16]. Now it is clear that such a subjection of the body to
the soul and of the lower powers to reason, was not from nature; otherwise it
would have remained after sin; since even in the demons the natural gifts
remained after sin, as Dionysius declared (Div. Nom. iv). Hence it is clear
that also the primitive subjection by virtue of which reason was subject to
God, was not a merely natural gift, but a supernatural endowment of grace; for
it is not possible that the effect should be of greater efficiency than the
cause. Hence Augustine says (De Civ. Dei xiii, 13) that, "as soon as they
disobeyed the Divine command, and forfeited Divine grace, they were ashamed of
their nakedness, for they felt the impulse of disobedience in the flesh, as
though it were a punishment corresponding to their own disobedience."
Hence if the loss of grace dissolved
--------------------------
P2-1, Q8, A1 - Whether the will is of good only?
Objection 1: It would seem that the will is not of good only. For
the same power regards opposites; for instance, sight regards white and black.
But good and evil are opposites. Therefore the will is not only of good, but
also of evil.
Objection 2: Further, rational powers can be directed to opposite
purposes, according to the Philosopher (Metaph. ix, 2). But the will is a
rational power, since it is "in the reason," as is stated in De Anima
iii, 9. Therefore the will can be directed to opposites; and consequently its
volition is not confined to good, but extends to evil.
Objection 3: Further, good and being are convertible. But volition
is directed not only to beings, but also to non-beings. For sometimes we wish
"not to walk," or "not to speak"; and again at times we
wish for future things, which are not actual beings. Therefore the will is not
of good only.
On the contrary, Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "evil is
outside the scope of the will," and that "all things desire
good."
I answer that, The will is a rational appetite. Now every appetite
is only of something good. The reason of this is that the appetite is nothing
else than an inclination of a person desirous of a thing towards that thing.
Now every inclination is to something like and suitable to the thing inclined.
Since, therefore, everything, inasmuch as it is being and substance, is a good,
it must needs be that every inclination is to something good. And hence it is
that the Philosopher says (Ethic. i, 1) that "the good is that which all
desire."
But it must be noted that, since every inclination results from a
form, the natural appetite results from a form existing in the nature of
things: while the sensitive appetite, as also the intellective or rational
appetite, which we call the will, follows from an apprehended form. Therefore,
just as the natural appetite tends to good existing in a thing; so the animal
or voluntary appetite tends to a good which is apprehended. Consequently, in
order that the will tend to anything, it is requisite, not that this be good in
very truth, but that it be apprehended as good. Wherefore the Philosopher says
(Phys. ii, 3) that "the end is a good, or an apparent good."
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q18, A1 - Whether every human action is good, or are there
evil actions?
Objection 1: It would seem that every human action is good, and
that none is evil. For Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that evil acts not, save
in virtue of the good. But no evil is done in virtue of the good. Therefore no
action is evil.
Objection 2: Further, nothing acts except in so far as it is in
act. Now a thing is evil, not according as it is in act, but according as its
potentiality is void of act; whereas in so far as its potentiality is perfected
by act, it is good, as stated in Metaph. ix, 9. Therefore nothing acts in so
far as it is evil, but only according as it is good. Therefore every action is
good, and none is evil.
Objection 3: Further, evil cannot be a cause, save accidentally,
as Dionysius declares (Div. Nom. iv). But every action has some effect which is
proper to it. Therefore no action is evil, but every action is good.
On the contrary, Our Lord said (Jn. 3:20): "Every one that
doth evil, hateth the light." Therefore some actions of man are evil.
I answer that, We must speak of good and evil in actions as of
good and evil in things: because such as everything is, such is the act that it
produces. Now in things, each one has so much good as it has being: since good
and being are convertible, as was stated in the FP, Question [5], Articles
[1],3. But God alone has the whole plenitude of His Being in a certain unity: whereas
every other thing has its proper fulness of being in a certain multiplicity.
Wherefore it happens with some things, that they have being in some respect,
and yet they are lacking in the fulness of being due to them. Thus the fulness
of human being requires a compound of soul and body, having all the powers and
instruments of knowledge and movement: wherefore if any man be lacking in any
of these, he is lacking in something due to the fulness of his being. So that
as much as he has of being, so much has he of goodness: while so far as he is
lacking in goodness, and is said to be evil: thus a blind man is possessed of
goodness inasmuch as he lives; and of evil, inasmuch as he lacks sight. That,
however, which has nothing of being or goodness, could not be said to be either
evil or good. But since this same fulness of being is of the very essence of
good, if a thing be lacking in its due fulness of being, it is not said to be
good simply, but in a certain respect, inasmuch as it is a being; although it
can be called a being simply, and a non-being in a certain respect, as was
stated in the FP, Question [5], Article [1], ad 1. We must therefore say that
every action has goodness, in so far as it has being; whereas it is lacking in
goodness, in so far as it is lacking in something that is due to its fulness of
being; and thus it is said to be evil: for instance if it lacks the quantity
determined by reason, or its due place, or something of the kind.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q18, A2 - Whether the good or evil of a man's action is
derived from its object?
Objection 1: It would seem that the good or evil of an action is
not derived from its object. For the object of any action is a thing. But
"evil is not in things, but in the sinner's use of them," as
Augustine says (De Doctr. Christ. iii, 12). Therefore the good or evil of a
human action is not derived from their object.
Objection 2: Further, the object is compared to the action as its
matter. But the goodness of a thing is not from its matter, but rather from the
form, which is an act. Therefore good and evil in actions is not derived from
their object.
Objection 3: Further, the object of an active power is compared to
the action as effect to cause. But the goodness of a cause does not depend on
its effect; rather is it the reverse. Therefore good or evil in actions is not
derived from their object.
On the contrary, It is written (Osee 9:10): "They became
abominable as those things which they loved." Now man becomes abominable
to God on account of the malice of his action. Therefore the malice of his
action is according to the evil objects that man loves. And the same applies to
the goodness of his action.
I answer that, as stated above (Article [1]) the good or evil of
an action, as of other things, depends on its fulness of being or its lack of
that fulness. Now the first thing that belongs to the fulness of being seems to
be that which gives a thing its species. And just as a natural thing has its
species from its form, so an action has its species from its object, as
movement from its term. And therefore just as the primary goodness of a natural
thing is derived from its form, which gives it its species, so the primary
goodness of a moral action is derived from its suitable object: hence some call
such an action "good in its genus"; for instance, "to make use
of what is one's own." And just as, in natural things, the primary evil is
when a generated thing does not realize its specific form (for instance, if
instead of a man, something else be generated); so the primary evil in moral
actions is that which is from the object, for instance, "to take what
belongs to another." And this action is said to be "evil in its
genus," genus here standing for species, just as we apply the term
"mankind" to the whole human species.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q18, A3 - Whether man's action is good or evil from a
circumstance?
Objection 1: It would seem that an action is not good or evil from
a circumstance. For circumstances stand around [circumstant] an action, as
being outside it, as stated above (Question [7], Article [1]). But "good
and evil are in things themselves," as is stated in Metaph. vi, 4. Therefore
an action does not derive goodness or malice from a circumstance.
Objection 2: Further, the goodness or malice of an action is
considered principally in the doctrine of morals. But since circumstances are
accidents of actions, it seems that they are outside the scope of art: because
"no art takes notice of what is accidental" (Metaph. vi, 2).
Therefore the goodness or malice of an action is not taken from a circumstance.
Objection 3: Further, that which belongs to a thing, in respect of
its substance, is not ascribed to it in respect of an accident. But good and
evil belong to an action in respect of its substance; because an action can be
good or evil in its genus as stated above (Article [2]). Therefore an action is
not good or bad from a circumstance.
On the contrary, the Philosopher says (Ethic. ii, 3) that a
virtuous man acts as he should, and when he should, and so on in respect of the
other circumstances. Therefore, on the other hand, the vicious man, in the
matter of each vice, acts when he should not, or where he should not, and so on
with the other circumstances. Therefore human actions are good or evil
according to circumstances.
I answer that, In natural things, it is to be noted that the whole
fulness of perfection due to a thing, is not from the mere substantial form,
that gives it its species; since a thing derives much from supervening
accidents, as man does from shape, color, and the like; and if any one of these
accidents be out of due proportion, evil is the result. So it is with action.
For the plenitude of its goodness does not consist wholly in its species, but
also in certain additions which accrue to it by reason of certain accidents:
and such are its due circumstances. Wherefore if something be wanting that is
requisite as a due circumstance the action will be evil.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q18, A4 - Whether a human action is good or evil from its
end?
Objection 1: It would seem that the good and evil in human actions
are not from the end. For Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "nothing acts
with a view to evil." If therefore an action were good or evil from its
end, no action would be evil. Which is clearly false.
Objection 2: Further, the goodness of an action is something in
the action. But the end is an extrinsic cause. Therefore an action is not said
to be good or bad according to its end.
Objection 3: Further, a good action may happen to be ordained to
an evil end, as when a man gives an alms from vainglory; and conversely, an
evil action may happen to be ordained to a good end, as a theft committed in
order to give something to the poor. Therefore an action is not good or evil
from its end.
On the contrary, Boethius says (De Differ. Topic. ii) that
"if the end is good, the thing is good, and if the end be evil, the thing
also is evil."
I answer that, The disposition of things as to goodness is the
same as their disposition as to being. Now in some things the being does not
depend on another, and in these it suffices to consider their being absolutely.
But there are things the being of which depends on something else, and hence in
their regard we must consider their being in its relation to the cause on which
it depends. Now just as the being of a thing depends on the agent, and the
form, so the goodness of a thing depends on its end. Hence in the Divine
Persons, Whose goodness does not depend on another, the measure of goodness is
not taken from the end. Whereas human actions, and other things, the goodness
of which depends on something else, have a measure of goodness from the end on
which they depend, besides that goodness which is in them absolutely.
Accordingly a fourfold goodness may be considered in a human
action. First, that which, as an action, it derives from its genus; because as
much as it has of action and being so much has it of goodness, as stated above
(Article [1]). Secondly, it has goodness according to its species; which is
derived from its suitable object. Thirdly, it has goodness from its
circumstances, in respect, as it were, of its accidents. Fourthly, it has
goodness from its end, to which it is compared as to the cause of its goodness.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q18, A9 - Whether an individual action can be indifferent?
Objection 1: It would seem that an individual action can be
indifferent. For there is no species that does not, cannot, contain an
individual. But an action can be indifferent in its species, as stated above
(Article [8]). Therefore an individual action can be indifferent.
Objection 2: Further, individual actions cause like habits, as
stated in Ethic. ii, 1. But a habit can be indifferent: for the Philosopher
says (Ethic. iv, 1) that those who are of an even temper and prodigal
disposition are not evil; and yet it is evident that they are not good, since
they depart from virtue; and thus they are indifferent in respect of a habit.
Therefore some individual actions are indifferent.
Objection 3: Further, moral good belongs to virtue, while moral
evil belongs to vice. But it happens sometimes that a man fails to ordain a
specifically indifferent action to a vicious or virtuous end. Therefore an
individual action may happen to be indifferent.
On the contrary, Gregory says in a homily (vi in Evang.): "An
idle word is one that lacks either the usefulness of rectitude or the motive of
just necessity or pious utility." But an idle word is an evil, because
"men . . . shall render an account of it in the day of judgment" (Mt.
12:36): while if it does not lack the motive of just necessity or pious
utility, it is good. Therefore every word is either good or bad. For the same
reason every other action is either good or bad. Therefore no individual action
is indifferent.
I answer that, It sometimes happens that an action is indifferent
in its species, but considered in the individual it is good or evil. And the
reason of this is because a moral action, as stated above (Article [3]),
derives its goodness not only from its object, whence it takes its species; but
also from the circumstances, which are its accidents, as it were; just as
something belongs to a man by reason of his individual accidents, which does
not belong to him by reason of his species. And every individual action must
needs have some circumstance that makes it good or bad, at least in respect of
the intention of the end. For since it belongs to the reason to direct; if an
action that proceeds from deliberate reason be not directed to the due end, it
is, by that fact alone, repugnant to reason, and has the character of evil. But
if it be directed to a due end, it is in accord with reason; wherefore it has
the character of good. Now it must needs be either directed or not directed to
a due end. Consequently every human action that proceeds from deliberate
reason, if it be considered in the individual, must be good or bad.
If, however, it does not proceed from deliberate reason, but from
some act of the imagination, as when a man strokes his beard, or moves his hand
or foot; such an action, properly speaking, is not moral or human; since this
depends on the reason. Hence it will be indifferent, as standing apart from the
genus of moral actions.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q74, A1 - Whether the will is a subject of sin?
Objection 1: It would seem that the will cannot be a subject of
sin. For Dionysius says (Div. Nom. iv) that "evil is outside the will and
the intention." But sin has the character of evil. Therefore sin cannot be
in the will.
Objection 2: Further, the will is directed either to the good or
to what seems good. Now from the fact that will wishes the good, it does not
sin: and that it wishes what seems good but is not truly good, points to a
defect in the apprehensive power rather than in the will. Therefore sin is
nowise in the will.
Objection 3: Further, the same thing cannot be both subject and
efficient cause of sin: because "the efficient and the material cause do
not coincide" (Phys. 2, text. 70). Now the will is the efficient cause of
sin: because the first cause of sinning is the will, as Augustine states (De
Duabus Anim. x, 10,11). Therefore it is not the subject of sin.
On the contrary, Augustine says (Retract. i, 9) that "it is
by the will that we sin, and live righteously."
I answer that, Sin is an act, as stated above (Question [71],
Articles [1],6). Now some acts pass into external matter, e.g. "to
cut" and "to burn": and such acts have for their matter and
subject, the thing into which the action passes: thus the Philosopher states
(Phys. iii, text. 18) that "movement is the act of the thing moved, caused
by a mover." On the other hand, there are acts which do not pass into
external matter, but remain in the agent, e.g. "to desire" and
"to know": and such are all moral acts, whether virtuous or sinful.
Consequently the proper subject of sin must needs be the power which is the
principle of the act. Now since it is proper to moral acts that they are
voluntary, as stated above (Question [1], Article [1]; Question [18], Article
[6]), it follows that the will, which is the principle of voluntary acts, both
of good acts, and of evil acts or sins, is the principle of sins. Therefore it
follows that sin is in the will as its subject.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q74, A2 - Whether the will alone is the subject of sin?
Objection 1: It would seem that the will alone is the subject of
sin. For Augustine says (De Duabus Anim. x, 10) that "no one sins except
by the will." Now the subject of sin is the power by which we sin.
Therefore the will alone is the subject of sin.
Objection 2: Further, sin is an evil contrary to reason. Now good
and evil pertaining to reason are the object of the will alone. Therefore the
will alone is the subject of sin.
Objection 3: Further, every sin is a voluntary act, because, as
Augustine states (De Lib. Arb. iii, 18) [*Cf. De Vera Relig. xiv.], "so
true is it that every sin is voluntary, that unless it be voluntary, it is no
sin at all." Now the acts of the other powers are not voluntary, except in
so far as those powers are moved by the will; nor does this suffice for them to
be the subject of sin, because then even the external members of the body,
which are moved by the will, would be a subject of sin; which is clearly
untrue. Therefore the will alone is the subject of sin.
On the contrary, Sin is contrary to virtue: and contraries are
about one same thing. But the other powers of the soul, besides the will, are
the subject of virtues, as stated above (Question [56]). Therefore the will is
not the only subject of sin.
I answer that, As was shown above (Article [1]), whatever is the a
principle of a voluntary act is a subject of sin. Now voluntary acts are not
only those which are elicited by the will, but also those which are commanded
by the will, as we stated above (Question [6], Article [4]) in treating of
voluntariness. Therefore not only the will can be a subject of sin, but also
all those powers which can be moved to their acts, or restrained from their
acts, by the will; and these same powers are the subjects of good and evil
moral habits, because act and habit belong to the same subject.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q74, A3 - Whether there can be sin in the sensuality?
Objection 1: It would seem that there cannot be sin in the
sensuality. For sin is proper to man who is praised or blamed for his actions.
Now sensuality is common to us and irrational animals. Therefore sin cannot be
in the sensuality.
Objection 2: Further, "no man sins in what he cannot
avoid," as Augustine states (De Lib. Arb. iii, 18). But man cannot prevent
the movement of the sensuality from being inordinate, since "the
sensuality ever remains corrupt, so long as we abide in this mortal life;
wherefore it is signified by the serpent," as Augustine declares (De Trin.
xii, 12,13). Therefore the inordinate movement of the sensuality is not a sin.
Objection 3: Further, that which man himself does not do is not
imputed to him as a sin. Now "that alone do we seem to do ourselves, which
we do with the deliberation of reason," as the Philosopher says (Ethic.
ix, 8). Therefore the movement of the sensuality, which is without the
deliberation of reason, is not imputed to a man as a sin.
On the contrary, It is written (Rm. 7:19): "The good which I
will I do not; but the evil which I will not, that I do": which words
Augustine explains (Contra Julian. iii, 26; De Verb. Apost. xii, 2,3), as
referring to the evil of concupiscence, which is clearly a movement of the
sensuality. Therefore there can be sin in the sensuality.
I answer that, As stated above (Articles [2],3), sin may be found
in any power whose act can be voluntary and inordinate, wherein consists the
nature of sin. Now it is evident that the act of the sensuality, or sensitive
appetite, is naturally inclined to be moved by the will. Wherefore it follows
that sin can be in the sensuality.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q74, A5 - Whether sin can be in the reason?
Objection 1: It would seem that sin cannot be in the reason. For
the sin of any power is a defect thereof. But the fault of the reason is not a
sin, on the contrary, it excuses sin: for a man is excused from sin on account
of ignorance. Therefore sin cannot be in the reason.
Objection 2: Further, the primary object of sin is the will, as
stated above (Article [1]). Now reason precedes the will, since it directs it.
Therefore sin cannot be in the reason.
Objection 3: Further, there can be no sin except about things
which are under our control. Now perfection and defect of reason are not among
those things which are under our control: since by nature some are mentally
deficient, and some shrewd-minded. Therefore no sin is in the reason.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Trin. xii, 12) that sin is in
the lower and in the higher reason.
I answer that, The sin of any power is an act of that power, as we
have clearly shown (Articles [1],2,3). Now reason has a twofold act: one is its
proper act in respect of its proper object, and this is the act of knowing the
truth; the other is the act of reason as directing the other powers. Now in
both of these ways there may be sin in the reason. First, in so far as it errs
in the knowledge of truth, which error is imputed to the reason as a sin, when
it is in ignorance or error about what it is able and ought to know: secondly,
when it either commands the inordinate movements of the lower powers, or
deliberately fails to check them.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q74, A8 - Whether consent to delectation is a mortal sin?
Objection 1: It would seem that consent to delectation is not a
mortal sin, for consent to delectation belongs to the lower reason, which does
not consider the eternal types, i.e. the eternal law, and consequently does not
turn away from them. Now every mortal sin consists in turning away from
Augustine's definition of mortal sin, which was quoted above (Question [71],
Article [6]). Therefore consent to delectation is not a mortal sin.
Objection 2: Further, consent to a thing is not evil, unless the
thing to which consent is given be evil. Now "the cause of anything being
such is yet more so," or at any rate not less. Consequently the thing to
which a man consents cannot be a lesser evil than his consent. But delectation
without deed is not a mortal sin, but only a venial sin. Therefore neither is
the consent to the delectation a mortal sin.
Objection 3: Further, delectations differ in goodness and malice,
according to the difference of the deeds, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. x,
3,5). Now the inward thought is one thing, and the outward deed, e.g.
fornication, is another. Therefore the delectation consequent to the act of
inward thought, differs in goodness and malice from the pleasure of
fornication, as much as the inward thought differs from the outward deed; and
consequently there is a like difference of consent on either hand. But the
inward thought is not a mortal sin, nor is the consent to that thought: and
therefore neither is the consent to the delectation.
Objection 4: Further, the external act of fornication or adultery
is a mortal sin, not by reason of the delectation, since this is found also in
the marriage act, but by reason of an inordinateness in the act itself. Now he
that consents to the delectation does not, for this reason, consent to the
inordinateness of the act. Therefore he seems not to sin mortally.
Objection 5: Further, the sin of murder is more grievous than
simple fornication. Now it is not a mortal sin to consent to the delectation
resulting from the thought of murder. Much less therefore is it a mortal sin to
consent to the delectation resulting from the thought of fornication.
Objection 6: Further, the Lord's prayer is recited every day for
the remission of venial sins, as Augustine asserts (Enchiridion lxxviii). Now
Augustine teaches that consent to delectation may be driven away by means of
the Lord's Prayer: for he says (De Trin. xii, 12) that "this sin is much
less grievous than if it be decided to fulfil it by deed: wherefore we ought to
ask pardon for such thoughts also, and we should strike our breasts and say:
'Forgive us our trespasses.'" Therefore consent to delectation is a venial
sin.
On the contrary, Augustine adds after a few words: "Man will
be altogether lost unless, through the grace of the Mediator, he be forgiven
those things which are deemed mere sins of thought, since without the will to
do them, he desires nevertheless to enjoy them." But no man is lost except
through mortal sin. Therefore consent to delectation is a mortal sin.
I answer that, There have been various opinions on this point, for
some have held that consent to delectation is not a mortal sin, but only a
venial sin, while others have held it to be a mortal sin, and this opinion is
more common and more probable. For we must take note that since every
delectation results from some action, as stated in Ethic. x, 4, and again, that
since every delectation may be compared to two things, viz. to the operation
from which it results, and to the object in which a person takes delight. Now
it happens that an action, just as a thing, is an object of delectation,
because the action itself can be considered as a good and an end, in which the
person who delights in it, rests. Sometimes the action itself, which results in
delectation, is the object of delectation, in so far as the appetitive power,
to which it belongs to take delight in anything, is brought to bear on the
action itself as a good: for instance, when a man thinks and delights in his
thought, in so far as his thought pleases him; while at other times the delight
consequent to an action, e.g. a thought, has for its object another action, as
being the object of his thought; and then his thought proceeds from the
inclination of the appetite, not indeed to the thought, but to the action
thought of. Accordingly a man who is thinking of fornication, may delight in
either of two things: first, in the thought itself, secondly, in the
fornication thought of. Now the delectation in the thought itself results from
the inclination of the appetite to the thought; and the thought itself is not
in itself a mortal sin; sometimes indeed it is only a venial sin, as when a man
thinks of such a thing for no purpose; and sometimes it is no sin at all, as
when a man has a purpose in thinking of it; for instance, he may wish to preach
or dispute about it. Consequently such affection or delectation in respect of
the thought of fornication is not a mortal sin in virtue of its genus, but is
sometimes a venial sin and sometimes no sin at all: wherefore neither is it a
mortal sin to consent to such a thought. In this sense the first opinion is
true.
But that a man in thinking of fornication takes pleasure in the
act thought of, is due to his desire being inclined to this act. Wherefore the
fact that a man consents to such a delectation, amounts to nothing less than a
consent to the inclination of his appetite to fornication: for no man takes
pleasure except in that which is in conformity with his appetite. Now it is a
mortal sin, if a man deliberately chooses that his appetite be conformed to
what is in itself a mortal sin. Wherefore such a consent to delectation in a
mortal sin, is itself a mortal sin, as the second opinion maintains.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q110, A1 - Whether grace implies anything in the soul?
Objection 1: It would seem that grace does not imply anything in
the soul. For man is said to have the grace of God even as the grace of man.
Hence it is written (Gn. 39:21) that the Lord gave to Joseph "grace
[Douay: 'favor'] in the sight of the chief keeper of the prison." Now when
we say that a man has the favor of another, nothing is implied in him who has
the favor of the other, but an acceptance is implied in him whose favor he has.
Hence when we say that a man has the grace of God, nothing is implied in his
soul; but we merely signify the Divine acceptance.
Objection 2: Further, as the soul quickens the body so does God
quicken the soul; hence it is written (Dt. 30:20): "He is thy life."
Now the soul quickens the body immediately. Therefore nothing can come as a
medium between God and the soul. Hence grace implies nothing created in the
soul.
Objection 3: Further, on Rm. 1:7, "Grace to you and
peace," the gloss says: "Grace, i.e. the remission of sins." Now
the remission of sin implies nothing in the soul, but only in God, Who does not
impute the sin, according to Ps. 31:2: "Blessed is the man to whom the
Lord hath not imputed sin." Hence neither does grace imply anything in the
soul.
On the contrary, Light implies something in what is enlightened.
But grace is a light of the soul; hence Augustine says (De Natura et Gratia
xxii): "The light of truth rightly deserts the prevaricator of the law,
and those who have been thus deserted become blind." Therefore grace
implies something in the soul.
I answer that, According to the common manner of speech, grace is
usually taken in three ways. First, for anyone's love, as we are accustomed to
say that the soldier is in the good graces of the king, i.e. the king looks on
him with favor. Secondly, it is taken for any gift freely bestowed, as we are
accustomed to say: I do you this act of grace. Thirdly, it is taken for the
recompense of a gift given "gratis," inasmuch as we are said to be
"grateful" for benefits. Of these three the second depends on the
first, since one bestows something on another "gratis" from the love
wherewith he receives him into his good "graces." And from the second
proceeds the third, since from benefits bestowed "gratis" arises
"gratitude."
Now as regards the last two, it is clear that grace implies
something in him who receives grace: first, the gift given gratis; secondly,
the acknowledgment of the gift. But as regards the first, a difference must be
noted between the grace of God and the grace of man; for since the creature's
good springs from the Divine will, some good in the creature flows from God's
love, whereby He wishes the good of the creature. On the other hand, the will
of man is moved by the good pre-existing in things; and hence man's love does
not wholly cause the good of the thing, but pre-supposes it either in part or
wholly. Therefore it is clear that every love of God is followed at some time
by a good caused in the creature, but not co-eternal with the eternal love. And
according to this difference of good the love of God to the creature is looked
at differently. For one is common, whereby He loves "all things that
are" (Wis. 11:25), and thereby gives things their natural being. But the
second is a special love, whereby He draws the rational creature above the
condition of its nature to a participation of the Divine good; and according to
this love He is said to love anyone simply, since it is by this love that God
simply wishes the eternal good, which is Himself, for the creature.
Accordingly when a man is said to have the grace of God, there is
signified something bestowed on man by God. Nevertheless the grace of God
sometimes signifies God's eternal love, as we say the grace of predestination,
inasmuch as God gratuitously and not from merits predestines or elects some;
for it is written (Eph. 1:5): "He hath predestinated us into the adoption
of children . . . unto the praise of the glory of His grace."
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q110, A2 - Whether grace is a quality of the soul?
Objection 1: It would seem that grace is not a quality of the
soul. For no quality acts on its subject, since the action of a quality is not
without the action of its subject, and thus the subject would necessarily act
upon itself. But grace acts upon the soul, by justifying it. Therefore grace is
not a quality.
Objection 2: Furthermore, substance is nobler than quality. But
grace is nobler than the nature of the soul, since we can do many things by
grace, to which nature is not equal, as stated above (Question [109], Articles
[1],2,3). Therefore grace is not a quality.
Objection 3: Furthermore, no quality remains after it has ceased
to be in its subject. But grace remains; since it is not corrupted, for thus it
would be reduced to nothing, since it was created from nothing; hence it is
called a "new creature"(Gal. 6:15).
On the contrary, on Ps. 103:15: "That he may make the face
cheerful with oil"; the gloss says: "Grace is a certain beauty of
soul, which wins the Divine love." But beauty of soul is a quality, even
as beauty of body. Therefore grace is a quality.
I answer that, As stated above (Article [1]), there is understood
to be an effect of God's gratuitous will in whoever is said to have God's
grace. Now it was stated (Question [109], Article [1]) that man is aided by
God's gratuitous will in two ways: first, inasmuch as man's soul is moved by
God to know or will or do something, and in this way the gratuitous effect in
man is not a quality, but a movement of the soul; for "motion is the act
of the mover in the moved." Secondly, man is helped by God's gratuitous will,
inasmuch as a habitual gift is infused by God into the soul; and for this
reason, that it is not fitting that God should provide less for those He loves,
that they may acquire supernatural good, than for creatures, whom He loves that
they may acquire natural good. Now He so provides for natural creatures, that
not merely does He move them to their natural acts, but He bestows upon them
certain forms and powers, which are the principles of acts, in order that they
may of themselves be inclined to these movements, and thus the movements
whereby they are moved by God become natural and easy to creatures, according
to Wis. 8:1: "she . . . ordereth all things sweetly." Much more
therefore does He infuse into such as He moves towards the acquisition of supernatural
good, certain forms or supernatural qualities, whereby they may be moved by Him
sweetly and promptly to acquire eternal good; and thus the gift of grace is a
quality.
------------------------------------------------------------------------
P2-1, Q110, A3 - Whether grace is the same as virtue?
Objection 1: It would seem that grace is the same as virtue. For
Augustine says (De Spir. et Lit. xiv) that "operating grace is faith that
worketh by charity." But faith that worketh by charity is a virtue.
Therefore grace is a virtue.
Objection 2: Further, what fits the definition, fits the defined.
But the definitions of virtue given by saints and philosophers fit grace, since
"it makes its subject good, and his work good," and "it is a
good quality of the mind, whereby we live righteously," etc. Therefore
grace is virtue.
Objection 3: Further, grace is a quality. Now it is clearly not in
the "fourth" species of quality; viz. "form" which is the
"abiding figure of things," since it does not belong to bodies. Nor
is it in the "third," since it is not a "passion nor a
passion-like quality," which is in the sensitive part of the soul, as is
proved in Physic. viii; and grace is principally in the mind. Nor is it in the
"second" species, which is "natural power" or
"impotence"; since grace is above nature and does not regard good and
evil, as does natural power. Therefore it must be in the "first"
species which is "habit" or "disposition." Now habits of
the mind are virtues; since even knowledge itself is a virtue after a manner,
as stated above (Question [57], Articles [1],2). Therefore grace is the same as
virtue.
On the contrary, If grace is a virtue, it would seem before all to
be one of the three theological virtues. But grace is neither faith nor hope,
for these can be without sanctifying grace. Nor is it charity, since
"grace foreruns charity," as Augustine says in his book on the
Predestination of the Saints (De Dono Persev. xvi). Therefore grace is not
virtue.
I answer that, Some held that grace and virtue were identical in
essence, and differed only logically---in the sense that we speak of grace
inasmuch as it makes man pleasing to God, or is given gratuitously---and of
virtue inasmuch as it empowers us to act rightly. And the Master seems to have
thought this (Sent. ii, D 27).
But if anyone rightly considers the nature of virtue, this cannot
hold, since, as the Philosopher says (Physic. vii, text. 17), "virtue is
disposition of what is perfect---and I call perfect what is disposed according
to its nature." Now from this it is clear that the virtue of a thing has
reference to some pre-existing nature, from the fact that everything is
disposed with reference to what befits its nature. But it is manifest that the
virtues acquired by human acts of which we spoke above (Question [55], seqq.)
are dispositions, whereby a man is fittingly disposed with reference to the
nature whereby he is a man; whereas infused virtues dispose man in a higher
manner and towards a higher end, and consequently in relation to some higher
nature, i.e. in relation to a participation of the Divine Nature, according to
2 Pt. 1:4: "He hath given us most great and most precious promises; that
by these you may be made partakers of the Divine Nature." And it is in
respect of receiving this nature that we are said to be born again sons of God.
And thus, even as the natural light of reason is something besides
the acquired virtues, which are ordained to this natural light, so also the
light of grace which is a participation of the Divine Nature is something
besides the infused virtues which are derived from and are ordained to this
light, hence the Apostle says (Eph. 5:8): "For you were heretofore
darkness, but now light in the Lord. Walk then as children of the light."
For as the acquired virtues enable a man to walk, in accordance with the
natural light of reason, so do the infused virtues enable a man to walk as
befits the light of grace.
=================
Summa Contra Gentiles B3, A159 : Of God and His Creatures
How Man is delivered from Sin BECAUSE man cannot return to one
opposite without retiring from the other, to return to the state of
righteousness he must withdraw from sin, whereby he had declined from
righteousness. And because it is chiefly by the will that man is set on the way
to his last end, or turned away therefrom, he must not only withdraw from sin
in exterior act by ceasing to sin, but he must further withdraw in will, that
so he may rise again by grace. Now withdrawal of the will from sin means at
once repentance for the past and a resolution to avoid sin in future. For if a
man did not purpose to cease from sin, sin as it is in itself (or sin in
general) would not be contrary to his will. If he were minded to cease from
sin, but had no sorrow for sin past, that same particular sin of which he was
guilty would not be against his will.* Now the will must withdraw from sin by
taking the course contrary to that which led it into sin. But it was led into
sin by appetite and delight in inferior things. Therefore it must withdraw from
sin by certain penal inflictions. As delight drew it to consent to sin, so
these inflictions strengthen it in abomination of sin. When then man by grace
has obtained pardon for his sin and has been restored to the state of grace, he
still remains bound by God's justice to some punishment for his sin. If of his
own will he exacts this punishment of himself, he is thereby said to 'make
satisfaction' to God, inasmuch as by punishing himself for his sin he fulfils
with labour and pain the order instituted of heaven, which order he had
transgressed by sinning and following his own will. But if he does not exact
this punishment of himself it will be inflicted by God, since the domain of
divine providence cannot be suffered to lie in disorder. The punishment in that
case will not be called 'satisfactory,' since it will not be of the choice of
the sufferer, but it will be called 'purificatory,' or 'purgatorial,' because
he will be purified and purged by another punishing him; and so whatever was
inordinate in him will be brought back to due order. Hence the Apostle says: If
we were to judge ourselves, we should not be judged: but while we are judged,
we are chastised by the Lord, that we may not be condemned with this world (1
Cor. xi, 31). Nevertheless, in the process of conversion, the disgust for sin
and the fixing of the affections on God may be so intense as that there shall
remain no outstanding liability to punishment. For the punishment which one
suffers after the forgiveness of sin is necessary to bring the mind to cleave
more firmly to good, -- punishments being medicines, -- as also for the
observance of the order of justice in the punishment of the sinner. But love of
God, especially when it is vehement and strong, is sufficient to establish
man's mind in good; and intense disgust for a past fault carries with it great
sorrow for the same. Hence by the vehemence of the love of God and hatred for
sin there is excluded any further need of satisfactory or purgatorial
punishment.* And though the vehemence be not so great as totally to bar the
punishment, nevertheless, the greater the vehemence, so much less of punishment
will suffice. But what we do through our friends we are reckoned to do of
ourselves, inasmuch as friendship makes two one in heart, and this is especially
true of the love of charity: therefore, as a man may make satisfaction to God
of himself, so also may he do it through another, especially in case of
necessity: for the punishment which his friend suffers on his account he
reckons as his own punishment; and thus punishment is not wanting to him in
that he has compassion for the sufferings of his friend, and that all the more
for his being the cause of his friend's suffering. And again the affection of
charity in him who suffers for his friend makes his satisfaction more
acceptable to God than it would be if he were suffering for his own doings: for
the one is an effort of spontaneous charity, the other an acquiescence in
necessity. Hence we learn that one man may make satisfaction for another,
provided both of them be in charity. Hence the saying of the Apostle: Bear ye
one another's burdens, and so ye shall fulfil the law of Christ (Gal. vi, 2).
=================
CATECHISM OF THE CATHOLIC CHURCH
THE DIGNITY OF THE HUMAN PERSON
I. MERCY AND SIN
1846 The Gospel is the revelation in Jesus Christ of God's mercy
to sinners.113 The angel announced to Joseph: "You shall call his name
Jesus, for he will save his people from their sins."114 The same is true
of the Eucharist, the sacrament of redemption: "This is my blood of the
covenant, which is poured out for many for the forgiveness of sins."115
1847 "God created us without us: but he did not will to save
us without us."116 To receive his mercy, we must admit our faults.
"If we say we have no sin, we deceive ourselves, and the truth is not in
us. If we confess our sins, he is faithful and just, and will forgive our sins
and cleanse us from all unrighteousness."117
1848 As St. Paul affirms, "Where sin increased, grace
abounded all the more."118 But to do its work grace must uncover sin so as
to convert our hearts and bestow on us "righteousness to eternal life
through Jesus Christ our Lord."119 Like a physician who probes the wound
before treating it, God, by his Word and by his Spirit, casts a living light on
sin:
Conversion requires convincing of sin; it includes the interior
judgment of conscience, and this, being a proof of the action of the Spirit of
truth in man's inmost being, becomes at the same time the start of a new grant
of grace and love: "Receive the Holy Spirit." Thus in this
"convincing concerning sin" we discover a double gift: the gift of
the truth of conscience and the gift of the certainty of redemption. The Spirit
of truth is the Consoler.120
II. THE DEFINITION OF SIN
1849 Sin is an offense against reason, truth, and right
conscience; it is failure in genuine love for God and neighbor caused by a
perverse attachment to certain goods. It wounds the nature of man and injures
human solidarity. It has been defined as "an utterance, a deed, or a
desire contrary to the eternal law."121
1850 Sin is an offense against God: "Against you, you alone,
have I sinned, and done that which is evil in your sight."122 Sin sets
itself against God's love for us and turns our hearts away from it. Like the
first sin, it is disobedience, a revolt against God through the will to become
"like gods,"123 knowing and determining good and evil. Sin is thus
"love of oneself even to contempt of God."124 In this proud self-
exaltation, sin is diametrically opposed to the obedience of Jesus, which
achieves our salvation.125
1851 It is precisely in the Passion, when the mercy of Christ is
about to vanquish it, that sin most clearly manifests its violence and its many
forms: unbelief, murderous hatred, shunning and mockery by the leaders and the
people, Pilate's cowardice and the cruelty of the soldiers, Judas' betrayal -
so bitter to Jesus, Peter's denial and the disciples' flight. However, at the
very hour of darkness, the hour of the prince of this world,126 the sacrifice
of Christ secretly becomes the source from which the forgiveness of our sins
will pour forth inexhaustibly.
III. THE DIFFERENT KINDS OF SINS
1852 There are a great many kinds of sins. Scripture provides
several lists of them. The Letter to the Galatians contrasts the works of the
flesh with the fruit of the Spirit: "Now the works of the flesh are plain:
fornication, impurity, licentiousness, idolatry, sorcery, enmity, strife,
jealousy, anger, selfishness, dissension, factions, envy, drunkenness,
carousing, and the like. I warn you, as I warned you before, that those who do
such things shall not inherit the Kingdom of God."127
1853 Sins can be distinguished according to their objects, as can
every human act; or according to the virtues they oppose, by excess or defect;
or according to the commandments they violate. They can also be classed
according to whether they concern God, neighbor, or oneself; they can be
divided into spiritual and carnal sins, or again as sins in thought, word,
deed, or omission. The root of sin is in the heart of man, in his free will,
according to the teaching of the Lord: "For out of the heart come evil
thoughts, murder, adultery, fornication, theft, false witness, slander. These
are what defile a man."128 But in the heart also resides charity, the
source of the good and pure works, which sin wounds.
IV. THE GRAVITY OF SIN: MORTAL AND VENIAL SIN
1854 Sins are rightly evaluated according to their gravity. The
distinction between mortal and venial sin, already evident in Scripture,129
became part of the tradition of the Church. It is corroborated by human
experience.
1855 Mortal sin destroys charity in the heart of man by a grave
violation of God's law; it turns man away from God, who is his ultimate end and
his beatitude, by preferring an inferior good to him.
Venial sin allows charity to subsist, even though it offends and
wounds it.
1856 Mortal sin, by attacking the vital principle within us - that
is, charity - necessitates a new initiative of God's mercy and a conversion of
heart which is normally accomplished within the setting of the sacrament of
reconciliation:
When the will sets itself upon something that is of its nature
incompatible with the charity that orients man toward his ultimate end, then
the sin is mortal by its very object ... whether it contradicts the love of
God, such as blasphemy or perjury, or the love of neighbor, such as homicide or
adultery. ... But when the sinner's will is set upon something that of its
nature involves a disorder, but is not opposed to the love of God and neighbor,
such as thoughtless chatter or immoderate laughter and the like, such sins are
venial.130
1857 For a sin to be mortal, three conditions must together be
met: "Mortal sin is sin whose object is grave matter and which is also
committed with full knowledge and deliberate consent."131
1858 Grave matter is specified by the Ten Commandments,
corresponding to the answer of Jesus to the rich young man: "Do not kill,
Do not commit adultery, Do not steal, Do not bear false witness, Do not
defraud, Honor your father and your mother."132 The gravity of sins is
more or less great: murder is graver than theft. One must also take into
account who is wronged: violence against parents is in itself graver than violence
against a stranger.
1859 Mortal sin requires full knowledge and complete consent. It
presupposes knowledge of the sinful character of the act, of its opposition to
God's law. It also implies a consent sufficiently deliberate to be a personal
choice. Feigned ignorance and hardness of heart133 do not diminish, but rather
increase, the voluntary character of a sin.
1860 Unintentional ignorance can diminish or even remove the
imputability of a grave offense. But no one is deemed to be ignorant of the
principles of the moral law, which are written in the conscience of every man.
The promptings of feelings and passions can also diminish the voluntary and
free character of the offense, as can external pressures or pathological
disorders. Sin committed through malice, by deliberate choice of evil, is the
gravest.
1861 Mortal sin is a radical possibility of human freedom, as is
love itself. It results in the loss of charity and the privation of sanctifying
grace, that is, of the state of grace. If it is not redeemed by repentance and
God's forgiveness, it causes exclusion from Christ's kingdom and the eternal
death of hell, for our freedom has the power to make choices for ever, with no
turning back. However, although we can judge that an act is in itself a grave offense,
we must entrust judgment of persons to the justice and mercy of God.
1862 One commits venial sin when, in a less serious matter, he
does not observe the standard prescribed by the moral law, or when he disobeys
the moral law in a grave matter, but without full knowledge or without complete
consent.
1863 Venial sin weakens charity; it manifests a disordered
affection for created goods; it impedes the soul's progress in the exercise of
the virtues and the practice of the moral good; it merits temporal punishment.
Deliberate and unrepented venial sin disposes us little by little to commit
mortal sin. However venial sin does not break the covenant with God. With God's
grace it is humanly reparable. "Venial sin does not deprive the sinner of
sanctifying grace, friendship with God, charity, and consequently eternal
happiness."134
While he is in the flesh, man cannot help but have at least some
light sins. But do not despise these sins which we call "light": if
you take them for light when you weigh them, tremble when you count them. A
number of light objects makes a great mass; a number of drops fills a river; a
number of grains makes a heap. What then is our hope? Above all, confession.135
1864 "Therefore I tell you, every sin and blasphemy will be forgiven
men, but the blasphemy against the Spirit will not be forgiven."136 There
are no limits to the mercy of God, but anyone who deliberately refuses to
accept his mercy by repenting, rejects the forgiveness of his sins and the
salvation offered by the Holy Spirit.137 Such hardness of heart can lead to
final impenitence and eternal loss.
V. THE PROLIFERATION OF SIN
1865 Sin creates a proclivity to sin; it engenders vice by
repetition of the same acts. This results in perverse inclinations which cloud
conscience and corrupt the concrete judgment of good and evil. Thus sin tends
to reproduce itself and reinforce itself, but it cannot destroy the moral sense
at its root.
1866 Vices can be classified according to the virtues they oppose,
or also be linked to the capital sins which Christian experience has
distinguished, following St. John Cassian and St. Gregory the Great. They are
called "capital" because they engender other sins, other vices.138
They are pride, avarice, envy, wrath, lust, gluttony, and sloth or acedia.
1867 The catechetical tradition also recalls that there are
"sins that cry to heaven": the blood of Abel,139 the sin of the
Sodomites,140 the cry of the people oppressed in Egypt,141 the cry of the
foreigner, the widow, and the orphan,142 injustice to the wage earner.143
1868 Sin is a personal act. Moreover, we have a responsibility for
the sins committed by others when we cooperate in them:
- by participating directly and voluntarily in them;
- by ordering, advising, praising, or approving them;
- by not disclosing or not hindering them when we have an
obligation to do so;
- by protecting evil-doers.
1869 Thus sin makes men accomplices of one another and causes
concupiscence, violence, and injustice to reign among them. Sins give rise to
social situations and institutions that are contrary to the divine goodness.
"Structures of sin" are the expression and effect of personal sins.
They lead their victims to do evil in their turn. In an analogous sense, they
constitute a "social sin."144